Clark Hull (1884-1952)
Clark Hull was born near
Akron, New York but spent most of his boyhood in Michigan. He attended the
academy associated with Alma College before enrolling at the University of
Wisconsin. In his 20s he contracted typhoid fever and polio, illnesses that
left him with lifelong disabilities including a withered leg. Gifted with
mechanical ability, he designed and made his own leg brace to compensate.
Later, he designed an automated correlation calculating machine (Hull, 1925) to
aid his work on aptitude testing. After holding a series of jobs, he returned
to Wisconsin and received a PhD in psychology in 1918. He remained there until
1929, when he moved to YaleÕs Institute of Human Relations as a research
professor. Before arriving at Yale, his research was eclectic and included
books on aptitude testing (Hull, 1928) and hypnosis and suggestibility (Hull,
1933). He also was interested in concept formation and verbal learning.
However, his interests turned strictly to rat learning after arriving at Yale.
He spent the rest of his career providing an alternative to TolmanÕs line of
research while providing a synthetic theory that combined aspects of
ThorndikeÕs law of effect and Pavlovian conditioning. Like Tolman, Hull
believed that much could be learned about human behavior by running laboratory
experiments using the white rat. Although his theory was extremely influential
during his lifetime it is of only historical interest today. Nevertheless, any
history of psychology that neglects or omits it is incomplete. Additionally,
failure to understand Hull and his influence makes it difficult to see properly
how subsequent attempts to understand learning developed.
Hull
wished to make psychology as scientific an enterprise as physics. His two
models were NewtonÕs Principia and
EuclidÕs Elements. From both he
adopted the hypothetico-deductive system
and the tight logic of inferred theorems constructed from a minimal set of a priori postulates and definitions. He
believed that psychology would
Marginal Definition: hypothetico-deductive
system-a
system using logic derived from a small, restricted set of given truths used to
deduce new, derived, and logically consistent statements. After, those
deductions are tested experimentally. Statements experimentally confirmed are
kept and the others are discarded.
only advance when theory and
observations were closely linked. Then, those types of investigations would
yield Òfacts of intrinsic importanceÓ while Òindicating the truth or falsity of
the theoretical system from which the phenomena were originally deducedÓ (Hull,
1935, p. 493). Later (pp. 512-513) he writes:
Scientific theory in its best sense consists of the strict
logical deduction from definite postulates of what should be observed under
specified conditions. If the deductions are lacking or are logically invalid,
there is no theory; if the deductions involve conditions of observation which
are impossible of attainment, the theory is metaphysical rather than
scientific; and if the deduced phenomenon is not observed when the conditions
are fulfilled, the theory is false.
Systematically, he set out
to do for psychology what Newton had done for physics and Euclid had done for
geometry. He used ThorndikeÕs law of effect and PavlovÕs analysis of classical
conditioning as a starting point. He retained WatsonÕs S-R model but added
intervening variables. He anchored his intervening variables, via operational
definitions, to both the S side and the R side of the S-R formulation,
something he claimed other theorists failed to do. In two major books (Hull,
1943; Hull, 1952), he specified the details of his system. True to his advice,
the later version incorporated theoretical changes forced by the accumulation
of new experimental data. His system was dynamic, designed to change in the
face of unexpected new data. In explicit contrast to TolmanÕs approach, Hull
wanted to explain learning through the interaction of stimulus variables and
intervening variables only. Purposive behavior had no place in his system.
Ultimately, his system failed to explain learning. But, while he was alive his
system inspired a large number of psychologists to pursue his vision of a
mechanistic explanation for learning. It is worthwhile to briefly examine some
of HullÕs variables and how they interacted.
HullÕs
System
HullÕs system was complex.
In its final Òrevision of the system a total of eighteen postulates and twelve
corollaries was produced. In accordance with the hypothetico-deductive
procedure that Hull intended to follow, these primary principles were to be
used deductively to predict secondary principles, such as goal gradient and latent
learningÓ (Marx & Hillix, 1963, p. 247). The basic structure of the system
consisted of three (see Figure 11.3) types of variables: stimulus variables,
organismic or intervening variables, and response variables. The four stimulus
variables were measurable. They
---------------Insert
Figure 11.3 about here[HullÕs system from Marx &
Hillix]---------------
were the number of reinforced
trials, stimulus deprivation level, stimulus intensity, and the size of the
reinforcer. Each of these, in turn was connected to a corresponding intervening
variable, habit strength sHr, drive D, stimulus intensity dynamism V, and incentive K, respectively. Together, those four variables accounted for
acquisition of a learned response, its maintenance, or its decline. Their mathematical
relationship was multiplicative, thus should any one of them drop to zero then
the product of all of them would be zero as well. Other intervening variables
accounted for extinction and spontaneous recovery, reactive inhibition Ir and conditioned inhibition sIr; individual differences, oscillation
sOr; and consistency of learned
response, threshold sLr. The mathematical equation of the
intervening variables above equaled yet another one, overall or net reaction
potential sær. The response variables,
too, were measurable. They were response latency str, amplitude A, number of responses until extinction n, and response probability p.
These last variables, naturally enough, were the ones measured as the rats
interacted with the laboratory apparatus under various experimental conditions.
Here are all of the intervening variables and their mathematical relationships
in the final version of HullÕs equation:
sær = (sHr x D x V x K) – Ir – sIr – sLr +/- sOr
The biggest change between
the final version and previous versions was the addition of incentive (K). Hull added incentive because of
experiments by Crespi (1942) that demonstrated that rats ran faster when the
food reward in the goal box was made larger and slower when it was made
smaller.
Hull was an S-R theorist. He believed that learning was strengthened by repetition (through habit strength) and that reinforcement was related to the satisfaction of internal drive states such as hunger and thirst. Extinction was accounted for by the rapid accumulation of reactive inhibition following unreinforced trials. Spontaneous recovery occurred because reactive inhibition was only temporary. Criticism of Hullian formulations led to further patchwork and repair of the theory. After HullÕs death in 1952 interest by others dropped considerably. His most prominent student, Kenneth Spence, carried on HullÕs tradition but very quickly dropped his support for the drive reduction view of reinforcement and was much less concerned about maintaining the formal structure Hull had created.