What Makes Behavior Analysis Radical?
Modified: 2024-05-28 7:02 PM CDST
- What is radical behaviorism, or, more aptly, behavior analysis? What
makes it "radical"?
- First, consider classic behaviorism of both the
Watsonian or Hullian variety.
- Each of those types of behaviorism
attempted to rid themselves completely of subjectivity.
- Watson even
explained thinking as sub-vocal thought, and looked for movement of
the vocal cords while subjects thought.
- Hull admitted to internal
states, but only as they could be operationally defined.
- So, hunger
was not a feeling but a level of food deprivation.
- But, Hull could
not effectively operationalize states such as love; therefore, such
topics had to be excluded from psychology.
- Both Watsonian and Hullian
behaviorism, then, were ineffective in dealing with mental issues.
- One response to this problem was the rise of cognitivism, but another
was Skinner's behavior analysis.
- The radical thing that Skinner did was to admit mental states into
behavioristic analyses, but in a subtle way.
- Those mental states were
not called mental states; rather, they were included as a
sub-category of the environment, and, further, limited to only one's
personal environment. (Note that many radical behaviorists or
behavior analysts would not agree to my categorizing the internal
environment as a mental state.)
- So, in Skinner's view, each of us is
affected by the external environment and by our own internal
environment.
- But, the rules of engagement, as it were, are exactly
the same in both, meaning that reinforcement, stimulus control, the
three-term contingency, in short, all of the constructs of behavior
analysis, apply equally well to both environments.
- Take the following
example, given by Jay Moore (personal communication).
- You are playing
tennis, and as you hit the ball, you say, "Keep your eyes on the
ball."
- Then, you notice that the ball lands in the court more often
when you do.
- So, you keep saying that phrase to yourself as you hit
the ball, or, the effect, keeping the ball in the court, is
reinforcing your private verbal behavior.
- But, consider what would
happen if you said the phrase but the ball was just as likely to hit
the net, the back fence, or the court.
- Then, that private verbal
behavior would not be reinforced and, eventually, you would not say
that to yourself anymore.
- Notice how it is the contingency, the fact
that the phrase and the behavior affect each other, that determines
the likelihood that the phrase will be repeated.
- Also, notice that
the phrase itself has no power over the behavior, nor does it have
separate status (ie. it is not a "mental event").
- Behavior analysts are fun to talk to because they seem to live in
two separate worlds.
- Like the rest of us, they have desires or
wishes, but, deep inside, they know better.
- They know that those
desires and wishes do not have power over them; they are just private
environmental events to be reinforced or extinguished.
- In research,
they are constantly on the lookout for contingencies of
reinforcement.
- In some fields, they have been wildly successful.
Look, for instance, at behavioral therapy and behavior modification.
- Cognitivists argue with behavior analysts most when it comes to
explaining complex behaviors.
- The issue is not whether a cognitivist
or a behavioral analyst can provide an explanation; both can.
- Rather,
the issue boils down to whether unobservables will be admitted as
explanatory aids.
- Behavior analysts do not admit them while
cognitivists do.
- Parsimony may ultimately decide between the two
types of explanation, and some compromise may evolve.
- For relatively
simple issues, behavior-analytic explanations may be more
parsimonious.
- However, for complex issues, where behavior-analytic
environmental constructions become laborious and unstable, then
cognitive constructs may be more parsimonious.
- Time may tell.
Back to Chapter 1 Lectures